On the Catholic Exchange, an article by Catholic
psychologist Greg Bottaro appeared warning of the dangers of “Emotional Pornography.” He argues that just as men fall prey to “physical
pornography,” women are especially susceptible to “emotional pornography”
in the form of romantic films and songs, which supposedly create in women
unrealistic expectations for how their romantic partners are supposed to
behave. The implication is that just as
physical pornography turns women into “sex objects,” emotional pornography
turns men into “romance objects” who exist solely for the gratification of
women’s emotional desires.
The notion is quite intriguing, especially given the truth
that unrealistic expectations of romantic love do pervade our culture. But I want to push back against the idea that
romantic films and songs constitute pornography in any meaningful way. The author’s argument is flawed for several
reasons. First, he does not provide a
clear definition of what constitutes pornography. Second, the definitions that he does provide
do not apply to romantic films or songs, primarily because he does not accurately identify what is objectified in romantic films and songs. This makes his attempt to compare true pornography with the romance portrayed in films and music deeply morally problematic.
The first definition the author gives for what constitutes
pornography is based on what it does: it “somehow” creates a “movement of
something in us.” He writes that
romantic music and movies constitute pornography because they “present an idea
to a woman that somehow moves something
in her" (emphasis mine). This is a vague and
unsettling definition of pornography’s supposed effects. It could, in theory, encompass everything
from the poetry of John Keats to the plays of William Shakespeare to the novels
of Jane Austen, right on down to episodes of The Bachelor and Taylor Swift’s latest hit. Heck, the Song of Solomon “moves something in
me” – does that make it pornography?
Clearly we need a more precise definition. Although the author provides no specific examples of a film or song that he thinks "emotionally pornographic" (aside from Twilight and The Notebook), he does try to specify what he means by pornography, saying that
“using sex to sell is a form of pornography.”
He goes on to indulge some sketchy etymology (“pornography” does not
come from a Latin root, and “prostitution” is not the Latin word for “price”),
and then he points out that pornography objectifies individuals by treating
them as the means to fulfill sexual ends.
He also asserts something some cultural theorists have also argued: that
pornography “presents fantasy as reality.”
We have several claims to examine here. First: that pornography uses sex to
sell. I find this definition imprecise. Pornography does not use sex to sell. What it
does is sell sex. It’s a subtle but important
distinction. Pornography seeks both to arouse desire and to gratify it instantaneously. Porn is its own gratification. It is selling a sexual experience, not using the temptation of a sexual experience to sell a product. Using sex
to sell is what advertisements do, such as those found at Victoria’s Secret or Abercrombie and Fitch. Advertisements arouse desire but do not
gratify it – rather, they point you to something else which will gratify those desires. Art, it has been argued, is distinguishable
from both porn and advertising in that it does not seek to arouse desire but rather seeks to enable people
to contemplate an aesthetic ideal. (1)
Naturally, the boundaries between pornography, advertising, and art have been heavily contested by theorists and philosophers, who question whether the boundaries exist at all. (Trying to get a group of social theorists to agree on anything is probably harder than getting a group of dogs to sing in harmony.) But perhaps we can agree that the meaning of a form of communication (be it a film or a song or a novel or a photograph) is determined in that shifty, elusive space between the intent of the communicator and the intent of the recipient of the communicated object.
Of course, intentionality itself is a contested subject. But let's speak, if we can, about the intention behind romantic films. The author of this article suggests that romantic films are intentionally "marketing" men for women, packaging "unrealistic" men who gratify their emotional desires, similar to the way that pornography markets and packages unrealistic women for men's sexual desires. Yet here I find that the author blurs the line between pornography and advertising. In his own assessment, the worst that could be claimed for romantic films is that they serve as an advertisement for romantic love, arousing desires in women and leaving them wanting more: “you walk away from these movies feeling like your life isn’t that great, your relationship isn’t measuring up, or somehow you won’t be happy until you find a Ryan Gosling character to sweep you off your feet.” This is what advertisements do. If this is the case (and I would agree with him here) I would argue that romantic films could be critiqued as a form of consumerism. But what is offered for sale is not objectified men, as the author seems to believe, but the idea of romantic love.
And this is key: the marketed item in romantic films is not men, but the idea of romantic love. Therein lies an important difference between the objectification of women in pornography and the supposed objectification of men in romantic films. Within the context of pornography, the objectification of women occurs because the identity of the woman doesn't matter. Her thoughts, feelings, and personality are all irrelevant so long as she performs the necessary motions with her body. She is objectified, commodified, "thingified." In romantic films, however, at least within the context of the story, the personality of the man matters. His thoughts and feelings are taken into account, and relationality is foremost. He is not an anonymous object, but a human being with an identity and a personality that matters to the story.
The difference is one between fantasy and imagination. The author argues that pornography creates a fantasy for men, and he equates this with the "fantasy" created by romantic films. But again, I think there's a distinction to be made. Cultural theorists have posited that another difference between pornography and art is that porn creates a fantasy world in which viewers can manipulate reality, becoming sexual gods who turn others into sex toys that they can control. In this it is the enemy of imagination: George Steiner argued, for instance, that in pornography "there is no respect for the reader" or viewer "whose imaginative means are set at nil" (76). Art, on the other hand, engages the imagination, providing a means for viewers to explore reality and gain insight into the different forms it can take. It seeks not to dominate or control reality but to allow viewers to plumb its depths in new ways.
This distinction is subjective and subtle, but still important. And the author’s own words reveal his failure to recognize the difference: “Just as you know that you will never be able to live up to (or down to) the level of women in porn, we feel deep down that we will never be able to live up to (or down to) the level of those men in the movies you love.” In physical porn, however, there’s nothing to “live up to” except to be a manipulated object of someone’s sexual desire. (Frankly, I find the generalization that women feel inadequate based on what men find in pornography absurd. Perhaps some women do, and we pity them. But women do not object to porn because they secretly wish they could be porn goddesses but can't attain that ideal.) In romantic songs and films, however, we see not a fantasy in which men are manipulated like objects, but an imagined ideal for what relationships could be like. This is not to suggest that the “ideal” presented in these films and stories should never be critiqued. Certainly they should, and women should be wary of accepting this marketed ideal as a standard for their own lives. But at their best, romantic songs and stories allow us to explore the various depths of expression that love can take, and to contemplate the beauty of love between a man and a woman. When they do that, romance becomes art, as it does in the hands of our best poets, playwrights, filmmakers, and novelists.
Naturally, the boundaries between pornography, advertising, and art have been heavily contested by theorists and philosophers, who question whether the boundaries exist at all. (Trying to get a group of social theorists to agree on anything is probably harder than getting a group of dogs to sing in harmony.) But perhaps we can agree that the meaning of a form of communication (be it a film or a song or a novel or a photograph) is determined in that shifty, elusive space between the intent of the communicator and the intent of the recipient of the communicated object.
Of course, intentionality itself is a contested subject. But let's speak, if we can, about the intention behind romantic films. The author of this article suggests that romantic films are intentionally "marketing" men for women, packaging "unrealistic" men who gratify their emotional desires, similar to the way that pornography markets and packages unrealistic women for men's sexual desires. Yet here I find that the author blurs the line between pornography and advertising. In his own assessment, the worst that could be claimed for romantic films is that they serve as an advertisement for romantic love, arousing desires in women and leaving them wanting more: “you walk away from these movies feeling like your life isn’t that great, your relationship isn’t measuring up, or somehow you won’t be happy until you find a Ryan Gosling character to sweep you off your feet.” This is what advertisements do. If this is the case (and I would agree with him here) I would argue that romantic films could be critiqued as a form of consumerism. But what is offered for sale is not objectified men, as the author seems to believe, but the idea of romantic love.
And this is key: the marketed item in romantic films is not men, but the idea of romantic love. Therein lies an important difference between the objectification of women in pornography and the supposed objectification of men in romantic films. Within the context of pornography, the objectification of women occurs because the identity of the woman doesn't matter. Her thoughts, feelings, and personality are all irrelevant so long as she performs the necessary motions with her body. She is objectified, commodified, "thingified." In romantic films, however, at least within the context of the story, the personality of the man matters. His thoughts and feelings are taken into account, and relationality is foremost. He is not an anonymous object, but a human being with an identity and a personality that matters to the story.
The difference is one between fantasy and imagination. The author argues that pornography creates a fantasy for men, and he equates this with the "fantasy" created by romantic films. But again, I think there's a distinction to be made. Cultural theorists have posited that another difference between pornography and art is that porn creates a fantasy world in which viewers can manipulate reality, becoming sexual gods who turn others into sex toys that they can control. In this it is the enemy of imagination: George Steiner argued, for instance, that in pornography "there is no respect for the reader" or viewer "whose imaginative means are set at nil" (76). Art, on the other hand, engages the imagination, providing a means for viewers to explore reality and gain insight into the different forms it can take. It seeks not to dominate or control reality but to allow viewers to plumb its depths in new ways.
This distinction is subjective and subtle, but still important. And the author’s own words reveal his failure to recognize the difference: “Just as you know that you will never be able to live up to (or down to) the level of women in porn, we feel deep down that we will never be able to live up to (or down to) the level of those men in the movies you love.” In physical porn, however, there’s nothing to “live up to” except to be a manipulated object of someone’s sexual desire. (Frankly, I find the generalization that women feel inadequate based on what men find in pornography absurd. Perhaps some women do, and we pity them. But women do not object to porn because they secretly wish they could be porn goddesses but can't attain that ideal.) In romantic songs and films, however, we see not a fantasy in which men are manipulated like objects, but an imagined ideal for what relationships could be like. This is not to suggest that the “ideal” presented in these films and stories should never be critiqued. Certainly they should, and women should be wary of accepting this marketed ideal as a standard for their own lives. But at their best, romantic songs and stories allow us to explore the various depths of expression that love can take, and to contemplate the beauty of love between a man and a woman. When they do that, romance becomes art, as it does in the hands of our best poets, playwrights, filmmakers, and novelists.
Because, in my view, the author fails to identify the difference between the marketing of women in pornography and the marketing of romantic love in romantic films, he falls into dangerous moral territory. I find any comparison that tries to draw an
equation of any sort between the
so-called victims of emotional pornography (i.e., men who feel inadequate that
they can’t live up to the romantic expectations of their partners) and the
victims of real pornography (i.e., the countless women who are bought and sold
as slaves to the sex industry) deeply offensive and disturbing. I cannot find it in my heart to pity the poor
men who feel victimized that they can’t be as romantic as Ryan Gosling in The Notebook, not when men, women, and children around the world are heartlessly being traded like anonymous commodities every day. The type of objectification is simply not
the same, and it is morally repugnant and philosophically irresponsible to
suggest otherwise.
------------------------------------
(1) There's a great deal of debate within the realm of philosophy, art history, and cultural theory about the tenuous line between art and pornography. I don't mean to engage them here, except to suggest that Dr. Bottaro's thinking might be clarified if he considered the broader debates surrounding the topic he's engaging. See, for instance, Hans Maes' Art and Pornography: Philosophical Essays.